đ„ NEW YEAR SALE: 50% OFF Quillette Membership for the First 3 Months đ„
Learn more
→
Why Everyone Values Freedom
If a pregnant woman has the legal option to abort but is unable to raise a child in her financial circumstances, she has fewer meaningful choices than a woman who lives in a society with legal abortion and generously state-subsidized childcare.
On March 28, presidential candidate Bernie Sanders uploaded a video to YouTube entitled âMedicare for All Is about Freedom.â This may strike some viewers as an abuse of language. In a market system, a consumer can freely choose whether or not to pay Aetna or Blue Cross Blue Shield or no one for health insurance. In a single-payer system of Medicare for All, everyone with taxable income pays Medicare for health insuranceâtheirs and everyone elseâsâwhether or not any individual tax-payer wants to be part of that âAll.â Such a system may serve many social goods. It may even save most individual taxpayers money. (If X is your current tax burden, Y is the current cost of your private health insurance plan, and Z is the cost of your tax burden after the implementation of Medicare for All, the question that matters for your bottom line is whether Z comes to a figure more or less than the combined cost of X and Y.) It may, however, be difficult for conservatives to understand the contention of many progressive thinkersâfrom Karl Marx to Amartya Senâthat the provision of these social goods enhances not just the welfare and equality of many individuals but their real freedom.
Conservative thinkers have argued that the provision of these benefits must surely come at a price of reduced personal freedom. Consider the following thought experiment. An oddly conscientious thief steals my car and leaves more money stacked in my driveway than I would have likely received had I put the car on sale. This, however, doesnât detract from the objectionable involuntariness of the theft. More systematically, in his classic Anarchy, State and Utopia, the philosopher Robert Nozick adapted the thinking of classical liberals such as Locke and Kant to make the argument that only a libertarian âminimal stateâ can be justified. A state which appropriates private property to pay for social services, outside of developing the institutions of a minimal state providing security and the rule of law, is involved in a form of unjustifiable coercion. Effectively, state officials have decided that an individualâs liberty to use their property as they see fit can be superseded by the social goods which emerged from redistributive efforts. According to Nozick (at least at the time, given he shifted his political orientation), this is comparable to a form of benign slavery.
Our contention is that neither side of this debate is playing fast and loose with language. Instead, the two sides are separated by a sincere difference of opinion about how best to conceptualize freedom. This dispute about âfreedomâ isnât new in American politics. In his book Before the Storm, the historian of conservativism Rick Perlstein points out that civil rights protestors and supporters of Republican Presidential candidate Barry Goldwater both chanted about freedom. They did so despite taking opposite positions on such crucial issues as the provisions of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 compelling private businesses to desegregate against the will of their owners. Even more dramatically, an anti-communist thumbing through the Collected Works of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels for the first time might be startled to find that while Marx and Engels hardly ever talk about âjusticeâ or âequality,â they do talk quite a bit about âfreedom.â
So whatâs the right way to understand freedom? We both have strong views on the semantic issue and its moral and political implications, but we wonât try to settle any of those arguments here. Instead, we hope to illuminate the difference between negative or formal freedom and positive or substantive freedom so that readers can better understand what the dispute is about in the first place.
The Conservative Approach to Freedom
The conception of formal freedom holds that freedom is best analyzed and understood in terms of property. This tradition has its roots in the philosophy of John Locke and comes to fruition in the work of twentieth century libertarian thinkers like Robert Nozick and Murray Rothbard. We have a right to do what we want with our own bodies and labor because we own ourselves. As Locke articulated in the Second Treatise on Government, when we mix our labor with the world around us, we acquire âexternalâ property. Our rights to this property then need to be protected by a government, the primary duty of which is to ensure we can enjoy the fruits of our labor without coercion by others. In the best iterations of this approach, slavery, forced labor, and the forcible confiscation of the fruits of oneâs labor are all considered violations of the laborerâs property rights. Indeed, some libertarian thinkers have gone so far as to suggest that all three violations are morally on a par.
Mainstream conservatives donât go that far. They typically believe that freedom has to be balanced against other important values like tradition, stability, and social cohesion. This is frequently characterized as an âordered libertyâ approach to distributive justice and society, and receives its classic exposition in the work of Edmund Burke. Even so, a libertarian-like understanding of freedom is an important part of contemporary Anglo-American conservativism. Hereâs Ronald Reagan in an interview with Reason magazine five years before he was elected President:
The basis of conservatism is a desire for less government interference or less centralized authority or more individual freedom and this is a pretty general description also of what libertarianism is.
Now, I canât say that I will agree with all the things that the present group who call themselves Libertarians in the sense of a party say, because I think that like in any political movement there are shades, and there are libertarians who are almost over at the point of wanting no government at all or anarchy. I believe there are legitimate government functionsâŠ. We have government to insure [sic] that we donât each one of us have to carry a club to defend ourselves. But again, I stand on my statement that I think that libertarianism and conservatism are travelling the same path.
Perhaps the most well known analysis was given by the Austrian economist F.A. Hayek in his popular polemic, The Road to Serfdom. Written and published in the 1940s, as governments were expanding to fight fascist aggression, Hayek worried that this expansion would not retreat once the conflict ended. Instead, driven by well-meaning but misguided and controlling technocrats, the state would continue to expand under the auspices of securing a higher quality of life for all and rectifying unjustifiable inequalities. Unfortunately, because these technocrats do not truly understand the relationship between economic growth and liberty, they will cause ongoing damage and in fact generate declining standards of living for all. This will inevitably lead to the technocrats seizing more and more power to rectify the very problems they produced, eventually leading to a decline in freedom for all. This is why, in The Constitution of Liberty, Hayek argued that only a minimal state can both guarantee freedom and secure prosperity for most. While considerable inequalities will emerge in such a social context, many of them not predicated on merit but luck, this is preferable to the damage which would be caused by seeking greater equality.
As leftists, this makes perfect sense to us. We believe that substantive (as opposed to merely formal) freedom is best served by a left-wing economic program. This is because freedom is not exclusively about non-coercion by government or other individuals, which is only part of a more complex whole. Freedom is also about how capable one is of making choices to pursue various life goals. Acute precarity or lack of resources, for instance, can severely limit freedom by curtailing the number of choices available to an individual. A bumper sticker sold by the Libertarian Party bears the slogan âPro-Choice About Everything.â From our perspective, however, the Libertarian Party isnât as meaningfully pro-choice as the socialist Leftâeven on the narrow issue of abortion. If a pregnant woman has the legal option to abort but is unable to raise a child in her financial circumstances, she has fewer meaningful choices than a woman who lives in a society with legal abortion and generously state-subsidized childcare.
In this vein, Amartya Sen has argued that freedom is not just about non-interference, but about the availability of meaningful choices. While negative freedom is certainly one important kind of freedom, is isnât the only one. Even someone who feels the pull of the Lockean freedom championed by Reagan might see how, for example, the passage of the Americans with Disabilities Act in 1990 increased freedom in Senâs sense. That said, a more conservative interlocutor might suspect equivocation. The stand-up comedian and libertarian podcaster Dave Smith, who recently debated one of the authors of this piece, put it this way: âWe might describe the experience of flying in an airplane as being âfree from the ground,â but surely this doesnât have much to do with the political meaning of âfreedom.ââ
We believe that the best way for the Left to meet this challengeâand, indeed, the way in which various historically important left-wing writers have met itâis to argue that a more expansive understanding of freedom is more relevant to political principles like freedom from coercion. If a boss tells an employeeâespecially an unskilled employee in a time of high unemploymentââgo on a date with me or youâre fired,â this isnât as coercive as âgo on a date with me or Iâll kill youâ and it might not even be as effectively coercive as âgo on a date with me or Iâll tell everyone what you did,â but the degree of coercion is considerably greater than zero. If the employee is a member of a union, or even if they benefit from a national health insurance plan and so donât have to worry about losing their insurance if they lose their job, then that degree is dialed down a notch or two.
The conception of freedom as a meaningful and practical freedom from domination by others is sometimes called the ârepublican theory of liberty.â (Thatâs ârepublicanâ as in the Roman Republic, not the GOP.) While Locke understood freedom as non-interference, thinkers in this âneo-Romanâ tradition understand freedom as non-domination. Frank Lovett describesthis tradition of interpreting the republicans of classical antiquity in an article for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
Undoubtedly, the classical republicans were committed to the importance of active political participation, civic virtue, combating corruption, and so forth. But rather than viewing these as intrinsically valuable components of a particular vision of the good life, these authors argued, they should instead be viewed as instrumentally useful tools for securing and preserving political liberty, understood as independence from arbitrary rule. Republicanism, on this view, has its roots not in an Aristotelian vision of the ancient Greek polis, but rather in Roman jurisprudence with its fundamental and categorical distinction between free men and citizens on the one hand, and dependent slaves on the other.
To use a standard example in this tradition, slaves beaten by their master every day are interfered with more than slaves whose master treats them more kindly. Even so, itâs implausible that the latter are more free.
As Quentin Skinner observed, Karl Marxâs critique of capitalism falls well within this âneo-Romanâ tradition. (Indeed, from âwage slaveryâ to the idea of a temporary âdictatorshipâ of the proletariat, Roman political vocabulary looms large in Marxâs thought.) If most people born into a capitalist society lack the financial resources to start a business of their own (and most small businesses fail in their first year of operation), most people have little realistic choice but to go to work for others. Marxâs solution was to advocate the confiscation of businesses from their owners in favor of a system based on workersâ control of the means of production. Even many left-wing authors who stop short of that kind of radicalismâmuch as Ronald Reagan fell short of wanting to do away with all government in the name of non-interferenceâsee the issue of working-class people being vulnerable to arbitrary rule on the job as a major concern.
Social democrats propose that this kind of domination can be usefully lessened with redistributive social programs that make workers less dependent on business-owners. (If the government provide tuition-free higher education at public universities, someone considering saying ânoâ to an unreasonable request from his boss doesnât have to worry that they wonât be able to pay their childrenâs way through college. If Medicare for All has been instituted, they wonât have to worry about losing their health insurance. Given sufficiently worker-friendly labor laws, they may not even lose their job.) Whether such programs are worth the cost in government interference in the market depends not just on how we weigh the importance of freedom relative to other values but on how we understand the meaning of âfreedomâ in the first place.